-
[5][54] That is, science is open to the possibility that future experiments might support more complex theories than demanded by current data and is more interested in designing
experiments to discriminate between competing theories than favoring one theory over another based merely on philosophical principles. -
If the latter interpretation is accepted, the validity of Occam’s razor as a tool could possibly be accepted if the simpler hypotheses led to correct conclusions more often
than not. -
Another interpretation of the razor’s statement would be that “simpler hypotheses are generally better than the complex ones”.
-
“[27] Justifications Aesthetic[edit] Prior to the 20th century, it was a commonly held belief that nature itself was simple and that simpler hypotheses about nature were thus
more likely to be true. -
Science prefers the simplest explanation that is consistent with the data available at a given time, but the simplest explanation may be ruled out as new data become available.
-
“[3] This philosophical razor advocates that when presented with competing hypotheses about the same prediction and both theories have equal explanatory power one should prefer
the hypothesis that requires the fewest assumptions[4] and that this is not meant to be a way of choosing between hypotheses that make different predictions. -
Critics of the cladistic approach often observe that for some types of data, parsimony could produce the wrong results, regardless of how much data is collected (this is called
statistical inconsistency, or long branch attraction). -
However, this criticism is also potentially true for any type of phylogenetic inference, unless the model used to estimate the tree reflects the way that evolution actually
happened. -
‘”[41] Richard Swinburne[edit] Richard Swinburne argues for simplicity on logical grounds: … the simplest hypothesis proposed as an explanation of phenomena is more likely
to be the true one than is any other available hypothesis, that its predictions are more likely to be true than those of any other available hypothesis, and that it is an ultimate a priori epistemic principle that simplicity is evidence for
truth. -
If one accepts the first interpretation, the validity of Occam’s razor as a tool would then have to be rejected if the more complex explanations were more often correct than
the less complex ones (while the converse would lend support to its use). -
Dawkins argues the way evolution works is that the genes propagated in most copies end up determining the development of that particular species, i.e., natural selection turns
out to select specific genes, and this is really the fundamental underlying principle that automatically gives individual and group selection as emergent features of evolution. -
— Swinburne 1997 According to Swinburne, since our choice of theory cannot be determined by data (see Underdetermination and Duhem–Quine thesis), we must rely on some criterion
to determine which theory to use. -
Since it is absurd to have no logical method for settling on one hypothesis amongst an infinite number of equally data-compliant hypotheses, we should choose the simplest
theory: “Either science is irrational [in the way it judges theories and predictions probable] or the principle of simplicity is a fundamental synthetic a priori truth. -
In the related concept of overfitting, excessively complex models are affected by statistical noise (a problem also known as the bias–variance tradeoff), whereas simpler models
may capture the underlying structure better and may thus have better predictive performance. -
[55] It has been suggested that Occam’s razor is a widely accepted example of extraevidential consideration, even though it is entirely a metaphysical assumption.
-
However, science has shown repeatedly that future data often support more complex theories than do existing data.
-
[53][54][55] When scientists use the idea of parsimony, it has meaning only in a very specific context of inquiry.
-
[39] The idea here is that a simple theory applies to more cases than a more complex one, and is thus more easily falsifiable.
-
Thus, complex hypotheses must predict data much better than do simple hypotheses before researchers reject the simple hypotheses.
-
For each accepted explanation of a phenomenon, there may be an extremely large, perhaps even incomprehensible, number of possible and more complex alternatives.
-
“[27] The idea of parsimony or simplicity in deciding between theories, though not the intent of the original expression of Occam’s razor, has been assimilated into common
culture as the widespread layman’s formulation that “the simplest explanation is usually the correct one. -
In doing so he is invoking a variant of Occam’s razor known as Morgan’s Canon: “In no case is an animal activity to be interpreted in terms of higher psychological processes,
if it can be fairly interpreted in terms of processes which stand lower in the scale of psychological evolution and development.” -
[35] Practical considerations and pragmatism[edit] See also: Pragmatism and Problem of induction Mathematical[edit] Main article: Akaike information criterion One justification
of Occam’s razor is a direct result of basic probability theory. -
[29] Ernst Mach formulated the stronger version of Occam’s razor into physics, which he called the Principle of Economy stating: “Scientists must use the simplest means of
arriving at their results and exclude everything not perceived by the senses. -
Even if some increases in complexity are sometimes necessary, there still remains a justified general bias toward the simpler of two competing explanations.
-
Elliott Sober[edit] The philosopher of science Elliott Sober once argued along the same lines as Popper, tying simplicity with “informativeness”: The simplest theory is the
more informative, in the sense that it requires less information to a question. -
[6] In this context, Einstein himself expressed caution when he formulated Einstein’s Constraint: “It can scarcely be denied that the supreme goal of all theory is to make
the irreducible basic elements as simple and as few as possible without having to surrender the adequate representation of a single datum of experience. -
[12] Robert Grosseteste, in Commentary on [Aristotle’s] the Posterior Analytics Books (Commentarius in Posteriorum Analyticorum Libros) (c. 1217–1220), declares: “That is
better and more valuable which requires fewer, other circumstances being equal… For if one thing were demonstrated from many and another thing from fewer equally known premises, clearly that is better which is from fewer because it makes
us know quickly, just as a universal demonstration is better than particular because it produces knowledge from fewer premises. -
[53][54][55] As a logical principle, Occam’s razor would demand that scientists accept the simplest possible theoretical explanation for existing data.
-
[54] If multiple models of natural law make exactly the same testable predictions, they are equivalent and there is no need for parsimony to choose a preferred one.
-
Nevertheless, the precise words sometimes attributed to William of Ockham, (Entities must not be multiplied beyond necessity),[16] are absent in his extant works;[17] this
particular phrasing comes from John Punch,[18] who described the principle as a “common axiom” (axioma vulgare) of the Scholastics. -
[clarification needed] Thomas Aquinas made this argument in the 13th century, writing, “If a thing can be done adequately by means of one, it is superfluous to do it by means
of several; for we observe that nature does not employ two instruments [if] one suffices. -
“[37] The use of “sharp” here is not only a tongue-in-cheek reference to the idea of a razor, but also indicates that such predictions are more accurate than competing predictions.
-
“[31] Beginning in the 20th century, epistemological justifications based on induction, logic, pragmatism, and especially probability theory have become more popular among
philosophers. -
Testing the razor[edit] The razor’s statement that “other things being equal, simpler explanations are generally better than more complex ones” is amenable to empirical testing.
-
The term razor refers to distinguishing between two hypotheses either by “shaving away” unnecessary assumptions or cutting apart two similar conclusions.
-
The procedure to test the former interpretation would compare the track records of simple and comparatively complex explanations.
-
Our preference for simplicity may be justified by its falsifiability criterion: we prefer simpler theories to more complex ones “because their empirical content is greater;
and because they are better testable”. -
If we fail to justify simplicity considerations on the basis of the context in which we use them, we may have no non-circular justification: “Just as the question ‘why be
rational?’ -
may have no non-circular answer, the same may be true of the question ‘why should simplicity be considered in evaluating the plausibility of hypotheses?
-
This is again comparing a simple theory to a more complex theory where both explain the data equally well.
-
[32][33][34] Any more complex theory might still possibly be true.
-
George C. Williams in his book Adaptation and Natural Selection (1966) argues that the best way to explain altruism among animals is based on low-level (i.e., individual)
selection as opposed to high-level group selection. -
“[22] Around 1960, Ray Solomonoff founded the theory of universal inductive inference, the theory of prediction based on observations – for example, predicting the next symbol
based upon a given series of symbols. -
The general principle of science is that theories (or models) of natural law must be consistent with repeatable experimental observations.
-
Several background assumptions are required for parsimony to connect with plausibility in a particular research problem.
-
Similarly in natural science, in moral science, and in metaphysics the best is that which needs no premises and the better that which needs the fewer, other circumstances
being equal. -
To understand why, consider that for each accepted explanation of a phenomenon, there is always an infinite number of possible, more complex, and ultimately incorrect, alternatives.
-
While it has been claimed that Occam’s razor is not found in any of William’s writings,[15] one can cite statements such as (“Plurality must never be posited without necessity”),
which occurs in his theological work on the Sentences of Peter Lombard (ed. -
Since failing explanations can always be burdened with ad hoc hypotheses to prevent them from being falsified, simpler theories are preferable to more complex ones because
they tend to be more testable. -
-
This notion was deeply rooted in the aesthetic value that simplicity holds for human thought and the justifications presented for it often drew from theology.
-
[7] Empirical[edit] Occam’s razor has gained strong empirical support in helping to converge on better theories (see Uses section below for some examples).
-
Altruism is defined by some evolutionary biologists (e.g., R. Alexander, 1987; W. D. Hamilton, 1964) as behavior that is beneficial to others (or to the group) at a cost to
the individual, and many posit individual selection as the mechanism that explains altruism solely in terms of the behaviors of individual organisms acting in their own self-interest (or in the interest of their genes, via kin selection). -
None of the papers provided a balance of evidence that complexity of method improved forecast accuracy.
-
Most of the time, however, Occam’s razor is a conservative tool, cutting out “crazy, complicated constructions” and assuring “that hypotheses are grounded in the science of
the day”, thus yielding “normal” science: models of explanation and prediction. -
That would be an example of regular natural selection – a phenomenon called “the selfish herd”.
-
Likelihood methods for phylogeny use parsimony as they do for all likelihood tests, with hypotheses requiring fewer differing parameters (i.e., numbers or different rates
of character change or different frequencies of character state transitions) being treated as null hypotheses relative to hypotheses requiring more differing parameters. -
Systematics is the branch of biology that attempts to establish patterns of relationship among biological taxa, today generally thought to reflect evolutionary history.
-
The model they propose balances the precision of a theory’s predictions against their sharpness, preferring theories that sharply make correct predictions over theories that
accommodate a wide range of other possible results. -
It is a mistake to think that there is a single global principle that spans diverse subject matter.
-
Science often does not demand arbitration or selection criteria between models that make the same testable predictions.
-
Later formulations[edit] To quote Isaac Newton, “We are to admit no more causes of natural things than such as are both true and sufficient to explain their appearances.
-
This endless supply of elaborate competing explanations, called saving hypotheses, cannot be technically ruled out – except by using Occam’s razor.
-
The probabilistic (Bayesian) basis for Occam’s razor is elaborated by David J. C. MacKay in chapter 28 of his book Information Theory, Inference, and Learning Algorithms,[36]
where he emphasizes that a prior bias in favor of simpler models is not required. -
Philosophers, he suggests, may have made the error of hypostatizing simplicity (i.e., endowed it with a sui generis existence), when it has meaning only when embedded in a
specific context (Sober 1992). -
In science, Occam’s razor is used as a heuristic to guide scientists in developing theoretical models rather than as an arbiter between published models.
-
The ways of God are not open to reason, for God has freely chosen to create a world and establish a way of salvation within it apart from any necessary laws that human logic
or rationality can uncover. -
It is, however, often difficult to deduce which part of the data is noise (cf.
Works Cited
[‘”Ockham’s razor does not say that the more simple a hypothesis, the better.”[85]
2. ^ “Today, we think of the principle of parsimony as a heuristic device. We don’t assume that the simpler theory is correct and the more complex one false. We know
from experience that more often than not the theory that requires more complicated machinations is wrong. Until proved otherwise, the more complex theory competing with a simpler explanation should be put on the back burner, but not thrown onto the
trash heap of history until proven false.”[85]
3. ^ “While these two facets of simplicity are frequently conflated, it is important to treat them as distinct. One reason for doing so is that considerations of parsimony and of elegance typically
pull in different directions. Postulating extra entities may allow a theory to be formulated more simply, while reducing the ontology of a theory may only be possible at the price of making it syntactically more complex.”[53]
4. Barry, C. M. (27
May 2014). “Who sharpened Occam’s Razor?”. Irish Philosophy. Archived from the original on 5 October 2022. Retrieved 5 August 2022.
5. ^ Schaffer, Jonathan (2015). “What Not to Multiply Without Necessity” (PDF). Australasian Journal of Philosophy.
93 (4): 644–664. doi:10.1080/00048402.2014.992447. S2CID 16923735. Archived (PDF) from the original on 9 September 2020. Retrieved 8 August 2019.
6. ^ Duignan, Brian. “Occam’s Razor”. Encyclopedia Britannica. Archived from the original on 25 September
2023. Retrieved 11 May 2021.
7. ^ Ball, Philip (11 August 2016). “The Tyranny of Simple Explanations”. The Atlantic. Archived from the original on 2 February 2023. Retrieved 2 February 2023.
8. ^ Jump up to:a b c Hugh G. Gauch, Scientific Method
in Practice, Cambridge University Press, 2003, ISBN 0-521-01708-4, ISBN 978-0-521-01708-4.
9. ^ Jump up to:a b c d e f Hoffman, Roald; Minkin, Vladimir I.; Carpenter, Barry K. (1997). “Ockham’s Razor and Chemistry”. Hyle: International Journal
for Philosophy of Chemistry. 3: 3–28. Archived from the original on 14 July 2018. Retrieved 30 May 2004.
10. ^ Jump up to:a b Sober, Elliott (2015). Ockam’s Razor: A User’s Manual. Cambridge University Press. p. 4. ISBN 978-1107692534.
11. ^
Roger Ariew, Ockham’s Razor: A Historical and Philosophical Analysis of Ockham’s Principle of Parsimony, 1976
12. ^ Jump up to:a b Johannes Poncius’s commentary on John Duns Scotus’s Opus Oxoniense, book III, dist. 34, q. 1. in John Duns Scotus
Opera Omnia, vol.15, Ed. Luke Wadding, Louvain (1639), reprinted Paris: Vives, (1894) p.483a
13. ^ Aristotle, Physics 189a15, On the Heavens 271a33. See also Franklin, op cit. note 44 to chap. 9.
14. ^ Charlesworth, M. J. (1956). “Aristotle’s
Razor”. Philosophical Studies. 6: 105–112. doi:10.5840/philstudies1956606.
15. ^ Jump up to:a b c Franklin, James (2001). The Science of Conjecture: Evidence and Probability before Pascal. The Johns Hopkins University Press. Chap 9. p. 241.
16. ^
Alistair Cameron Crombie, Robert Grosseteste and the Origins of Experimental Science 1100–1700 (1953) pp. 85–86
17. ^ “SUMMA THEOLOGICA: The existence of God (Prima Pars, Q. 2)”. Newadvent.org. Archived from the original on 28 April 2013. Retrieved
26 March 2013.
18. ^ Vallee, Jacques (11 February 2013). “What Ockham really said”. Boing Boing. Archived from the original on 31 March 2013. Retrieved 26 March 2013.
19. ^ Bauer, Laurie (2007). The linguistics Student’s Handbook. Edinburgh:
Edinburgh University Press. p. 155.
20. ^ Flew, Antony (1979). A Dictionary of Philosophy. London: Pan Books. p. 253.
21. ^ Crombie, Alistair Cameron (1959), Medieval and Early Modern Philosophy, Cambridge, MA: Harvard, Vol. 2, p. 30.
22. ^
“Ockham’s razor”. Encyclopædia Britannica. Encyclopædia Britannica Online. 2010. Archived from the original on 23 August 2010. Retrieved 12 June 2010.
23. ^ Hawking, Stephen (2003). On the Shoulders of Giants. Running Press. p. 731. ISBN 978-0-7624-1698-1.
Retrieved 24 February 2016.[permanent dead link]
24. ^ Primary source: Newton (2011, p. 387) wrote the following two “philosophizing rules” at the beginning of part 3 of the Principia 1726 edition.
Regula I. Causas rerum naturalium non-plures admitti
debere, quam quæ & veræ sint & earum phænomenis explicandis sufficient.
Regula II. Ideoque effectuum naturalium ejusdem generis eædem assignandæ sunt causæ, quatenus fieri potest.
25. ^ Logical Constructions. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford
University. 2016. Archived from the original on 26 January 2021. Retrieved 29 March 2011.
26. ^ Induction: From Kolmogorov and Solomonoff to De Finetti and Back to Kolmogorov JJ McCall – Metroeconomica, 2004 – Wiley Online Library.
27. ^ Jump
up to:a b Soklakov, A. N. (2002). “Occam’s Razor as a formal basis for a physical theory”. Foundations of Physics Letters. 15 (2): 107–135. arXiv:math-ph/0009007. Bibcode:2000math.ph…9007S. doi:10.1023/A:1020994407185. S2CID 14940740.
28. ^ Rathmanner,
Samuel; Hutter, Marcus (2011). “A philosophical treatise of universal induction”. Entropy. 13 (6): 1076–1136. arXiv:1105.5721. Bibcode:2011Entrp..13.1076R. doi:10.3390/e13061076. S2CID 2499910.
29. ^ Baker, Alan (25 February 2010). “Simplicity”.
In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2011 Edition). Archived from the original on 24 February 2021. Retrieved 6 April 2013.
30. ^ Jump up to:a b c “What is Occam’s Razor?”. math.ucr.edu. Archived from the original
on 6 July 2017.
31. ^ Stormy Dawn (17 July 2017). Everywhere The Soles of Your Feet Shall Tread. Archway. ISBN 9781480838024. Archived from the original on 28 October 2023. Retrieved 22 May 2017.
32. ^ Sotos, John G. (2006) [1991]. Zebra Cards:
An Aid to Obscure Diagnoses. Mt. Vernon, VA: Mt. Vernon Book Systems. ISBN 978-0-9818193-0-3.
33. ^ Becher, Erich (1905). “The Philosophical Views of Ernst Mach”. The Philosophical Review. 14 (5): 535–562. doi:10.2307/2177489. JSTOR 2177489.
34. ^
Pegis 1945.
35. ^ Stanovich, Keith E. (2007). How to Think Straight About Psychology. Boston: Pearson Education, pp. 19–33.
36. ^ “ad hoc hypothesis – The Skeptic’s Dictionary – Skepdic.com”. skepdic.com. Archived from the original on 27 April
2009.
37. ^ Swinburne 1997 and Williams, Gareth T, 2008.
38. ^ Green, K. C.; Armstrong, J. S. (2015). “Simple versus complex forecasting: The evidence”. Journal of Business Research. 68 (8): 1678–1685. doi:10.1016/j.jbusres.2015.03.026. Archived
from the original on 8 June 2020. Retrieved 22 January 2019.(subscription required)
39. ^ MacKay, David J. C. (2003). Information Theory, Inference, and Learning Algorithms (PDF). Bibcode:2003itil.book…..M. Archived (PDF) from the original on
15 September 2012.
40. ^ Jump up to:a b Jefferys, William H.; Berger, James O. (1991). “Ockham’s Razor and Bayesian Statistics” (PDF). American Scientist. 80 (1): 64–72. JSTOR 29774559. Archived (PDF) from the original on 4 March 2005. (preprint
available as “Sharpening Occam’s Razor on a Bayesian Strop”).
41. ^ James, Gareth; et al. (2013). An Introduction to Statistical Learning. springer. pp. 105, 203–204. ISBN 9781461471370.
42. ^ Popper, Karl (1992) [1934]. Logik der Forschung [The
Logic of Scientific Discovery] (2nd ed.). London: Routledge. pp. 121–132. ISBN 978-84-309-0711-3.
43. ^ Sober, Elliott (1975). Simplicity. Oxford: Clarendon Press. ISBN 978-0-19-824407-3.
44. ^ Sober, Elliott (2004). “What is the Problem of Simplicity?”.
In Zellner, Arnold; Keuzenkamp, Hugo A.; McAleer, Michael (eds.). Simplicity, Inference and Modeling: Keeping it Sophisticatedly Simple. Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press. pp. 13–31. ISBN 978-0-521-80361-8. Archived from the original on
28 October 2023. Retrieved 4 August 2012. Paper as PDF.
45. ^ Swinburne, Richard (1997). Simplicity as Evidence for Truth. Milwaukee, Wisconsin: Marquette University Press. ISBN 978-0-87462-164-8.
46. ^ Einstein, Albert (1905). “Does the Inertia
of a Body Depend Upon Its Energy Content?”. Annalen der Physik (in German). 323 (18): 639–41. Bibcode:1905AnP…323..639E. doi:10.1002/andp.19053231314. Archived from the original on 21 October 2019. Retrieved 21 October 2019.
47. ^ L. Nash, The
Nature of the Natural Sciences, Boston: Little, Brown (1963).
48. ^ de Maupertuis, P. L. M. (1744). Mémoires de l’Académie Royale (in French). p. 423.
49. ^ de Broglie, L. (1925). Annales de Physique (in French). pp. 22–128.
50. ^ RA Jackson,
Mechanism: An Introduction to the Study of Organic Reactions, Clarendon, Oxford, 1972.
51. ^ Carpenter, B. K. (1984). Determination of Organic Reaction Mechanism, New York: Wiley-Interscience.
52. ^ Einstein, Albert (1934). “On the Method of Theoretical
Physics”. Philosophy of Science. 1 (2): 165 [163–169]. doi:10.1086/286316. ISSN 0031-8248. JSTOR 184387. S2CID 44787169. Archived from the original on 22 January 2023. Retrieved 22 January 2023.
53. ^ Mettenheim, Christoph von (1998). Popper Versus
Einstein: On the Philosophical Foundations of Physics. Mohr Siebeck. p. 34. ISBN 978-3-16-146910-7. Archived from the original on 22 January 2023. Retrieved 22 January 2023.
54. ^ Geis, Gilbert; Geis, Professor Emeritus of Criminology Law and &
Society Gilbert; Bienen, Leigh B. (1998). Crimes of the Century: From Leopold and Loeb to O.J. Simpson. UPNE. p. 39. ISBN 978-1-55553-360-1. Archived from the original on 5 April 2023. Retrieved 10 February 2023.
55. ^ “Everything Should Be Made
as Simple as Possible, But Not Simpler”. 13 May 2011. Archived from the original on 29 May 2012.
56. ^ Jump up to:a b c Alan Baker (2010) [2004]. “Simplicity”. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. California: Stanford University. ISSN 1095-5054.
Archived from the original on 26 March 2014. Retrieved 22 January 2005.
57. ^ Jump up to:a b c d e Courtney, A.; Courtney, M. (2008). “Comments Regarding ‘On the Nature of Science'”. Physics in Canada. 64 (3): 7–8. arXiv:0812.4932. Bibcode:2008arXiv0812.4932C.
58. ^
Jump up to:a b c Sober, Elliott (1994). “Let’s Razor Occam’s Razor”. In Knowles, Dudley (ed.). Explanation and Its Limits. Cambridge University Press. pp. 73–93.
59. ^ Rabinowitz, Matthew; Myers, Lance; Banjevic, Milena; Chan, Albert; Sweetkind-Singer,
Joshua; Haberer, Jessica; McCann, Kelly; Wolkowicz, Roland (1 March 2006). “Accurate prediction of HIV-1 drug response from the reverse transcriptase and protease amino acid sequences using sparse models created by convex optimization”. Bioinformatics.
22 (5): 541–549. doi:10.1093/bioinformatics/btk011. ISSN 1367-4803. PMID 16368772.
60. ^ Paul Pojman (2009). “Ernst Mach”. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. California: Stanford University. ISSN 1095-5054. Archived from the original on 11
November 2020. Retrieved 4 October 2009.
61. ^ Sober, Elliot (1998). Reconstructing the Past: Parsimony, Evolution, and Inference (2nd ed.). Massachusetts Institute of Technology: The MIT Press. p. 7. ISBN 978-0-262-69144-4.
62. ^ Wiley, Edward
O. (1981). Phylogenetics: the theory and practice of phylogenetic systematics. Wiley and Sons Interscience.
63. ^ Brower, AVZ (2017). “Statistical consistency and phylogenetic inference: a brief review”. Cladistics. 34 (5): 562–567. doi:10.1111/cla.12216.
PMID 34649374.
64. ^ Brower &, Schuh (2021). Biological Systematics: Principles and Applications (3rd edn.). Cornell University Press.
65. ^ Crick 1988, p. 146.
66. ^ “William Ockham”. Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford. Archived from the
original on 7 October 2019. Retrieved 24 February 2016.
67. ^ Dale T Irvin & Scott W Sunquist. History of World Christian Movement Volume, I: Earliest Christianity to 1453, p. 434. ISBN 9781570753961.
68. ^ “SUMMA THEOLOGICA: The existence of
God (Prima Pars, Q. 2)”. Newadvent.org. Archived from the original on 28 April 2013. Retrieved 26 March 2013.
69. ^ McDonald 2005.
70. ^ Dawkins, Richard (1 January 2007). The God delusion. London: Black Swan. pp. 157–158. ISBN 978-0-552-77331-7.
71. ^
Schmitt, Carl; Schwab, George; Strong, Tracy B. (2005). Political Theology. University of Chicago Press. doi:10.7208/chicago/9780226738901.001.0001. ISBN 978-0-226-73889-5.
72. ^ p. 282, Mémoires du docteur F. Antommarchi, ou les derniers momens
de Napoléon Archived 14 May 2016 at the Wayback Machine, vol. 1, 1825, Paris: Barrois L’Ainé
73. ^ Tonry, Michael (2005). “Obsolescence and Immanence in Penal Theory and Policy” (PDF). Columbia Law Review. 105: 1233–1275. Archived from the original
(PDF) on 23 June 2006.
74. ^ Jump up to:a b Chris S. Wallace and David M. Boulton; Computer Journal, Volume 11, Issue 2, 1968 Page(s):185–194, “An information measure for classification.”
75. ^ Jump up to:a b Chris S. Wallace and David L. Dowe;
Computer Journal, Volume 42, Issue 4, Sep 1999 Page(s):270–283, “Minimum Message Length and Kolmogorov Complexity.”
76. ^ Nannen, Volker. “A short introduction to Model Selection, Kolmogorov Complexity and Minimum Description Length” (PDF). Archived
(PDF) from the original on 2 June 2010. Retrieved 3 July 2010.
77. ^ “Algorithmic Information Theory”. Archived from the original on 24 December 2007.
78. ^ Paul M. B. Vitányi and Ming Li; IEEE Transactions on Information Theory, Volume 46, Issue
2, Mar 2000 Page(s):446–464, “Minimum Description Length Induction, Bayesianism and Kolmogorov Complexity.”
79. ^ Standish, Russell K (2000). “Why Occam’s Razor”. Foundations of Physics Letters. 17 (3): 255–266. arXiv:physics/0001020. Bibcode:2004FoPhL..17..255S.
doi:10.1023/B:FOPL.0000032475.18334.0e. S2CID 17143230.
80. ^ Solomonoff, Ray (1964). “A formal theory of inductive inference. Part I.” Information and Control. 7 (1–22): 1964. doi:10.1016/s0019-9958(64)90223-2.
81. ^ Schmidhuber, J. (2006). “The
New AI: General & Sound & Relevant for Physics”. In Goertzel, B.; Pennachin, C. (eds.). Artificial General Intelligence. pp. 177–200. arXiv:cs.AI/0302012.
82. ^ Dowe, David L. (2008). “Foreword re C. S. Wallace”. Computer Journal. 51 (5): 523–560.
doi:10.1093/comjnl/bxm117. S2CID 5387092.
83. ^ David L. Dowe (2010): “MML, hybrid Bayesian network graphical models, statistical consistency, invariance and uniqueness. A formal theory of inductive inference.” Handbook of the Philosophy of Science
– (HPS Volume 7) Philosophy of Statistics, Elsevier 2010 Page(s):901–982. https://web.archive.org/web/20140204001435/http://citeseerx.ist.psu.edu/viewdoc/download?doi=10.1.1.185.709&rep=rep1&type=pdf
84. ^ Scott Needham and David L. Dowe (2001):”
Message Length as an Effective Ockham’s Razor in Decision Tree Induction.” Proc. 8th International Workshop on Artificial Intelligence and Statistics (AI+STATS 2001), Key West, Florida, U.S.A., January 2001 Page(s): 253–260 “2001 Ockham.pdf” (PDF).
Archived (PDF) from the original on 23 September 2015. Retrieved 2 September 2015.
85. ^ Adam, S., and Pardalos, P. (2019), No-free lunch Theorem: A review, in “Approximation and Optimization”, Springer, 57-82
86. ^ Wolpert, D.H (1995), On the
Bayesian “Occam Factors” Argument for Occam’s Razor, in “Computational Learning Theory and Natural Learning Systems: Selecting Good Models”, MIT Press
87. ^ Berners-Lee, Tim (4 March 2013). “Principles of Design”. World Wide Web Consortium. Archived
from the original on 15 June 2022. Retrieved 5 June 2022.
88. ^ Jump up to:a b Robert T. Carroll (12 September 2014). “Occam’s Razor”. The Skeptic’s Dictionary. Archived from the original on 1 March 2016. Retrieved 24 February 2016.
89. ^ Quine,
W V O (1961). “Two dogmas of empiricism”. From a logical point of view. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. pp. 20–46. ISBN 978-0-674-32351-3.
90. ^ Gross, F. (2019). Occam’s Razor in Molecular and Systems Biology. Philosophy of Science, 86(5),
1134-1145. doi:10.1086/705474
91. ^ Immanuel Kant (1929). Norman Kemp-Smith transl (ed.). The Critique of Pure Reason. Palgrave Macmillan. p. 92. Archived from the original on 16 May 2012. Retrieved 27 October 2012. Entium varietates non-temere
esse minuendas
92. ^ Gordon Woo (20 June 2011). Calculating Catastrophe. World Scientific. pp. 303–. ISBN 978-1-84816-893-0. Archived from the original on 28 October 2023. Retrieved 10 August 2021.
93. ^ Mazin, Igor (April 2022). “Inverse Occam’s
razor”. Nature Physics. 18 (4): 367–368. arXiv:2204.08284. doi:10.1038/s41567-022-01575-2. ISSN 1745-2481. S2CID 247832936. Archived from the original on 9 July 2023. Retrieved 9 July 2023.
94. ^ Korteweg, Leon (2 December 2016). “QED 2016 – verslag
van een lang weekend tussen skeptici”. Skepter (in Dutch). 29 (4). Stichting Skepsis: 45–46. Archived from the original on 18 October 2017. Retrieved 21 October 2017.
95. ^ Jump up to:a b Hyde, Deborah (2012). “The Skeptic Magazine Awards 2011:
Winners”. The Skeptic. Vol. 23, no. 4. Archived from the original on 23 October 2017.
Photo credit: https://www.flickr.com/photos/nahidv/14116826873/’]