-
[43] The Forms See also: Plato’s theory of Forms In the dialogues Socrates regularly asks for the meaning of a general term (e. g. justice, truth, beauty), and criticizes
those who instead give him particular examples, rather than the quality shared by all examples. -
His own most decisive philosophical influences are usually thought to have been, along with Socrates, the pre-Socratics Pythagoras, Heraclitus, and Parmenides, although few
of his predecessors’ works remain extant and much of what is known about these figures today derives from Plato himself. -
Many have interpreted Plato as stating – even having been the first to write – that knowledge is justified true belief, an influential view that informed future developments
in epistemology. -
[32] Aristotle suggests that Socrates’ idea of forms can be discovered through investigation of the natural world, unlike Plato’s Forms that exist beyond and outside the ordinary
range of human understanding. -
[90] Modern reception See also: Transmission of the Greek Classics Plato’s thought is often compared with that of his most famous student, Aristotle, whose reputation during
the Western Middle Ages so completely eclipsed that of Plato that the Scholastic philosophers referred to Aristotle as “the Philosopher”. -
[79] Whereas those classified as “early dialogues” often conclude in aporia, the so-called “middle dialogues” provide more clearly stated positive teachings that are often
ascribed to Plato such as the theory of Forms. -
[c] Influences Socrates Main article: Socratic problem Plato never speaks in his own voice in his dialogues; every dialogue except the Laws features Socrates, although many
dialogues, including the Timaeus and Statesman, feature him speaking only rarely. -
[80] It should, however, be kept in mind that many of the positions in the ordering are still highly disputed, and also that the very notion that Plato’s dialogues can or
should be “ordered” is by no means universally accepted,[81][e] though Plato’s works are still often characterized as falling at least roughly into three groups stylistically. -
[72] The text of Plato as received today apparently represents the complete written philosophical work of Plato, based on the first century AD arrangement of Thrasyllus of
Mendes. -
“[8] Born: 428/427 or 424/423 BC, Athens, Greece; Died: 348 BC (aged c. 75-76 or 79-80), Athens, Greece; Notable work: Euthyphro, Apology, Crito, Phaedo, Meno, Protagoras,
Gorgias, Symposium, Phaedrus, Parmenides, Theaetetus, Republic, Timaeus Laws; Era: Ancient Greek philosophy; School: Platonic Academy; Notable students: Aristotle; Main interests: Epistemology, Metaphysics Political philosophy; Notable ideas:
Allegory of the cave, Cardinal virtues, Form of the Good, Theory of forms, Divisions of the soul, Platonic love, Platonic solids Biography Little is known about Plato’s early life and education. -
“Platonism” and its theory of Forms (also known as ‘theory of Ideas;) denies the reality of the material world, considering it only an image or copy of the real world.
-
[42] Philosophy In Plato’s dialogues, Socrates and his company of disputants had something to say on many subjects, including several aspects of metaphysics.
-
Plato’s well-known answer rests upon the fundamental responsibility to seek wisdom, wisdom which leads to an understanding of the Form of the Good.
-
[13] Plato gives little biographical information, but refers at various points to some of his relatives with a great degree of precision, including his brothers, Adeimantus,
and Glaucon, in the Plato’s Republic. -
Plato views “The Good” as the supreme Form, somehow existing even “beyond being”.
-
[60][61][62] Plato made abundant use of mythological narratives in his own work;[63] It is generally agreed that the main purpose for Plato in using myths was didactic.
-
That the modern theory of justified true belief as knowledge, which Gettier addresses, is equivalent to Plato’s is accepted by some scholars but rejected by others.
-
“[67] Karl Popper, on the other hand, claims that dialectic is the art of intuition for “visualising the divine originals, the Forms or Ideas, of unveiling the Great Mystery
behind the common man’s everyday world of appearances. -
The soul See also: Plato’s theory of soul For Plato, as was characteristic of ancient Greek philosophy, the soul was that which gave life.
-
[47] He uses this idea of reincarnation to introduce the concept that knowledge is a matter of recollection of things acquainted with before one is born, and not of observation
or study. -
“[86] It is, however, said that Plato once disclosed this knowledge to the public in his lecture On the Good, in which the Good is identified with the One (the Unity), the
fundamental ontological principle. -
Scholars debate whether he intends the theory to be literally true, however.
-
Many of the greatest early modern scientists and artists who broke with Scholasticism, with the support of the Plato-inspired Lorenzo (grandson of Cosimo), saw Plato’s philosophy
as the basis for progress in the arts and sciences. -
[3] Legacy Unwritten doctrines Main articles: Plato’s unwritten doctrines and Allegorical interpretations of Plato Plato’s unwritten doctrines are,[83][84][85] according to
some ancient sources, the most fundamental metaphysical teaching of Plato, which he disclosed only orally, and some say only to his most trusted fellows, and which he may have kept secret from the public, although many modern scholars[who?] -
Albert Einstein suggested that the scientist who takes philosophy seriously would have to avoid systematization and take on many different roles, and possibly appear as a
Platonist or Pythagorean, in that such a one would have “the viewpoint of logical simplicity as an indispensable and effective tool of his research. -
Chronology No one knows the exact order Plato’s dialogues were written in, nor the extent to which some might have been later revised and rewritten.
-
[51][52] In the Sophist, Statesman, Republic, Timaeus, and the Parmenides, Plato associates knowledge with the apprehension of unchanging Forms and their relationships to
one another (which he calls “expertise” in dialectic), including through the processes of collection and division. -
In other words, if one derives one’s account of something experientially, because the world of sense is in flux, the views therein attained will be mere opinions.
-
[50] Plato also identified problems with the justified true belief definition in the Theaetetus, concluding that justification (or an “account”) would require knowledge of
difference, meaning that the definition of knowledge is circular. -
The first witness who mentions its existence is Aristotle, who in his Physics writes: “It is true, indeed, that the account he gives there [i.e.
-
In modern times, Alfred North Whitehead famously said: “the safest general characterization of the European philosophical tradition is that it consists of a series of footnotes
to Plato. -
His most famous contribution is the theory of forms (or ideas), which has been interpreted as advancing a solution to what is now known as the problem of universals.
-
Friedrich Nietzsche notoriously attacked Plato’s “idea of the good itself” along with many fundamentals of Christian morality, which he interpreted as “Platonism for the masses”
in Beyond Good and Evil (1886). -
A reason for not revealing it to everyone is partially discussed in Phaedrus where Plato criticizes the written transmission of knowledge as faulty, favouring instead the
spoken logos: “he who has knowledge of the just and the good and beautiful … will not, when in earnest, write them in ink, sowing them through a pen with words, which cannot defend themselves by argument and cannot teach the truth effectually. -
Although Socrates influenced Plato directly, the influence of Pythagoras, or in a broader sense, the Pythagoreans, such as Archytas also appears to have been significant.
-
[34][page needed] Pythagoreanism Main article: Pythagoreanism The mathematical and mystical teachings of the followers of Pythagoras exerted a strong influence on Plato.
-
[88] The most important aspect of this interpretation of Plato’s metaphysics is the continuity between his teaching and the Neoplatonic interpretation of Plotinus[f] or Ficino[g]
which has been considered erroneous by many but may in fact have been directly influenced by oral transmission of Plato’s doctrine. -
The precise relationship between Plato and Socrates remains an area of contention among scholars.
-
The works taken as genuine in antiquity but are now doubted by at least some modern scholars are: Alcibiades I (*),[d] Alcibiades II (‡), Clitophon (*), Epinomis (‡), Letters
(*), Hipparchus (‡), Menexenus (*), Minos (‡), Lovers (‡), Theages (‡) The following works were transmitted under Plato’s name in antiquity, but were already considered spurious by the 1st century AD: Axiochus, Definitions, Demodocus, Epigrams,
Eryxias, Halcyon, On Justice, On Virtue, Sisyphus. -
[64] He considered that only a few people were capable or interested in following a reasoned philosophical discourse, but men in general are attracted by stories and tales.
-
[27][28] While recalling a moral lesson about frugal living Seneca mentions the meaning of Plato’s name: “His very name was given him because of his broad chest.
-
[95] Criticism Many recent philosophers have also diverged from what some would describe as ideals characteristic of traditional Platonism.
-
Socrates elicits a fact concerning a geometrical construction from a slave boy, who could not have otherwise known the fact (due to the slave boy’s lack of education).
-
The idea that mathematics and, generally speaking, abstract thinking is a secure basis for philosophical thinking as well as “for substantial theses in science and morals”.
-
But other contemporary researchers contest the idea that Plato despised rhetoric and instead view his dialogues as a dramatization of complex rhetorical principles.
-
The platonic Republic might be related to the idea of “a tightly organized community of like-minded thinkers”, like the one established by Pythagoras in Croton.
-
The only Platonic work known to western scholarship was Timaeus, until translations were made after the fall of Constantinople, which occurred during 1453.
-
Martin Heidegger argued against Plato’s alleged obfuscation of Being in his incomplete tome, Being and Time (1927), and the philosopher of science Karl Popper argued in the
first volume of The Open Society and Its Enemies (1945) that Plato’s alleged proposal for a utopian political regime in the Republic was prototypically totalitarian. -
(10a) In the Protagoras dialogue it is argued through Socrates that virtue is innate and cannot be learned, that no one does bad on purpose, and to know what is good results
in doing what is good; that knowledge is virtue. -
The theory of Forms is first introduced in the Phaedo dialogue (also known as On the Soul), wherein Socrates disputes the pluralism of Anaxagoras, then the most popular response
to Heraclitus and Parmenides. -
-
Some scholars take this as an indication that Plato had by this date wearied of the narrated form.
-
[67] Simon Blackburn adopts the first, saying that Plato’s dialectic is “the process of eliciting the truth by means of questions aimed at opening out what is already implicitly
known, or at exposing the contradictions and muddles of an opponent’s position. -
The role of dialectic in Plato’s thought is contested but there are two main interpretations: a type of reasoning and a method of intuition.
-
According to this theory of Forms, there are these two kinds of things: the apparent world of material objects grasped by the senses, which constantly changes, and an unchanging
and unseen world of Forms, grasped by reason. -
He also tells us what the material substrate is of which the Forms are predicated in the case of sensible things, and the One in that of the Forms – that it is this the duality
(the Dyad), the Great and Small. -
On the other hand, if one derives one’s account of something by way of the non-sensible Forms, because these Forms are unchanging, so too is the account derived from them.
-
Although Platon was a fairly common name (31 instances are known from Athens alone),[25] the name does not occur in Plato’s known family line.
-
A variety of sources have given accounts of Plato’s death.
-
He introduced the concept of form as distinct from matter, and that the physical world is an imitation of an eternal mathematical world.
-
[b] Unlike the work of nearly all of his contemporaries, Plato’s entire body of work is believed to have survived intact for over 2,400 years.
-
the Dyad], and the essence is the One, since the numbers are derived from the Great and Small by participation in the One”.
-
The remaining dialogues are classified as “late” and are generally agreed to be difficult and challenging pieces of philosophy.
-
• Governing (Rulers or Philosopher Kings) – those who are intelligent, rational, self-controlled, in love with wisdom, well suited to make decisions for the community.
-
[44] Plato advocates a belief in the immortality of the soul, and several dialogues end with long speeches imagining the afterlife.
-
[75][76] Authenticity Thirty-five dialogues and thirteen letters (the Epistles) have traditionally been ascribed to Plato, though modern scholarship doubts the authenticity
of at least some of these.
Works Cited
[‘”Though influenced primarily by Socrates, to the extent that Socrates is usually the main character in many of Plato’s writings, he was also influenced by Heraclitus, Parmenides, and the Pythagoreans”[3]
2. ^ “…the subject of philosophy, as it
is often conceived – a rigorous and systematic examination of ethical, political, metaphysical, and epistemological issues, armed with a distinctive method – can be called his invention.”[4][5]
3. ^ From aristos and kleos
4. ^ (*) if there is
no consensus among scholars as to whether Plato is the author, and (‡) if most scholars agree that Plato is not the author of the work. The extent to which scholars consider a dialogue to be authentic is noted in Cooper 1997, pp. v–vi.
5. ^ Increasingly
in the most recent Plato scholarship, writers are skeptical of the notion that the order of Plato’s writings can be established with any precision.[82]
6. ^ Plotinus describes this in the last part of his final Ennead (VI, 9) entitled On the Good,
or the One (Περὶ τἀγαθοῦ ἢ τοῦ ἑνός). Jens Halfwassen states in Der Aufstieg zum Einen’ (2006) that “Plotinus’ ontology – which should be called Plotinus’ henology – is a rather accurate philosophical renewal and continuation of Plato’s unwritten
doctrine, i.e. the doctrine rediscovered by Krämer and Gaiser.”
7. ^ In one of his letters (Epistolae 1612) Ficino writes: “The main goal of the divine Plato … is to show one principle of things, which he called the One (τὸ ἕν)”, cf. Montoriola
1926, p. 147.
8. Jones 2006.
9. ^ “Plato FAQ: Plato’s real name”. www.plato-dialogues.org.
10. ^ Jump up to:a b Brickhouse & Smith.
11. ^ Kraut 2013
12. ^ “Plato and Aristotle: How Do They Differ?”. Britannica. “Plato (c. 428–c. 348 BCE)
and Aristotle (384–322 BCE) are generally regarded as the two greatest figures of Western philosophy”.
13. ^ Cooper, John M.; Hutchinson, D.S., eds. (1997): “Introduction.”
14. ^ Cooper 1997, p. vii.
15. ^ Whitehead 1978, p. 39.
16. ^ Diogenes
Laertius, Life of Plato, III
• Nails 2002, p. 53
Wilamowitz-Moellendorff 2005, p. 46
17. ^ Wilamowitz-Moellendorff 2005, p. 46.
18. ^ Nails 2002, p. 246.
19. ^ Notopoulos, James A. (1940). “Porphyry’s Life of Plato”. Classical Philology.
35 (3): 284–293. doi:10.1086/362396. ISSN 0009-837X. JSTOR 264394. S2CID 161160877.
20. ^ Veres, Máté (1 January 2019). “Sextus Empiricus, Against Those in the Disciplines. Translated with an introduction and notes by Richard Bett (Oxford University
Press, 2018)”. International Journal for the Study of Skepticism.
21. ^ Guthrie 1986, p. 11.
22. ^ Kahn 1996, p. 186.
23. ^ McEvoy 1984.
24. ^ Cairns 1961, p. xiii.
25. ^ Dillon 2003, pp. 1–3.
26. ^ Press 2000, p. 1.
27. ^ Riginos 1976,
p. 73.
28. ^ Diogenes Laertius, Book iii, 20 Archived 28 April 2014 at the Wayback Machine
29. ^ Riginos 1976, p. 194.
30. ^ Schall 1996.
31. ^ Jump up to:a b Riginos 1976, p. 195.
32. ^ Guthrie 1986, p. 12 (footnote).
33. ^ Sedley, David,
Plato’s Cratylus, Cambridge University Press 2003, pp. 21–22 Archived 3 March 2016 at the Wayback Machine.
34. ^ Diogenes Laertius, Life of Plato, IV
35. ^ Notopoulos 1939, p. 135
36. ^ Seneca, Epistulae, VI 58:29–30; translation by Robert
Mott Gummere
37. ^ Laërtius 1925, § 4.
38. ^ Strauss 1964, pp. 50–51.
39. ^ Metaphysics 987b1–11
40. ^ McPherran, M.L. (1998). The Religion of Socrates. Penn State Press. p. 268.
41. ^ Vlastos 1991.
42. ^ Metaphysics, 1.6.1 (987a)
43. ^
Tusc. Disput. 1.17.39.
44. ^ R.M. Hare, Plato in C.C.W. Taylor, R.M. Hare and Jonathan Barnes, Greek Philosophers, Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999 (1982), 103–189, here 117–119.
45. ^ Russell, Bertrand (1991).
History of Western Philosophy. Routledge. pp. 120–124. ISBN 978-0-415-07854-2.
46. ^ Calian, Florin George (2021). Numbers, Ontologically Speaking: Plato on Numerosity. Brill. ISBN 978-90-04-46722-4.
47. ^ Jump up to:a b c McFarlane, Thomas J.
“Plato’s Parmenides”. Integralscience. Archived from the original on 22 February 2017. Retrieved 12 February 2017.
48. ^ John Palmer (2019). “Parmenides”. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived
from the original on 20 October 2017. Retrieved 18 October 2017.
49. ^ Jump up to:a b Large, William. “Heraclitus”. Arasite. Archived from the original on 6 March 2017. Retrieved 3 March 2017.
50. ^ Francis Cornford, 1941. The Republic of Plato.
Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. xxv.
51. ^ See this brief exchange from the Phaedo: “What is it that, when present in a body, makes it living? – A soul.” Phaedo 105c.
52. ^ Plato, Timaeus 44d & 70
53. ^ Dorter 2006, p. 360.
54. ^ Jorgensen
2018 is perhaps the strongest opponent to interpretations on which Plato intends the theory literally. See Jorgensen, The Embodied Soul in Plato’s Later Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2018.
55. ^ Baird & Kaufmann 2008.
56. ^
Theaetetus 156a
57. ^ Fine 2003, p. 5.
58. ^ Theaetetus 210a–b
59. ^ McDowell 1973, p. 256.
60. ^ Taylor 2011, pp. 176–187.
61. ^ Lee 2011, p. 432.
62. ^ Taylor 2011, p. 189.
63. ^ Republic, Book IV.
64. ^ Blössner 2007, pp. 345–349.
65. ^
Blössner 2007, p. 350.
66. ^ Phaedrus (265a–c)
67. ^ Kastely, James (2015). The Rhetoric of Plato’s Republic. Chicago UP.
68. ^ Bjork, Collin (2021). “Plato, Xenophon, and the Uneven Temporalities of Ethos in the Trial of Socrates”. Philosophy
& Rhetoric. 54 (3): 240–262. doi:10.5325/philrhet.54.3.0240. ISSN 0031-8213. JSTOR 10.5325/philrhet.54.3.0240. S2CID 244334227.
69. ^ Bengtson, Erik (2019). The epistemology of rhetoric: Plato, doxa and post-truth. Uppsala.
70. ^ Chappel, Timothy.
“Mythos and Logos in Plato”. Open University. Retrieved 20 August 2017.
71. ^ Jorgensen, Chad. The Embodied Soul in Plato’s Later Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2018 page 199.
72. ^ Partenie, Catalin. “Plato’s Myths”. Stanford
Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on 27 May 2017. Retrieved 29 October 2017.
73. ^ Burnet 1928a, § 177.
74. ^ Jump up to:a b Blackburn 1996, p. 104.
75. ^ Popper 1962, p. 133.
76. ^ Brumbaugh & Wells 1989.
77. ^ Allen
1975, p. 12.
78. ^ Platonis opera quae extant omnia edidit Henricus Stephanus, Genevae, 1578.
79. ^ Suzanne 2009.
80. ^ Cooper 1997, pp. viii–xii.
81. ^ Irwin 2011, pp. 64 & 74
82. ^ Fine 1999a, p. 482.
83. ^ Complete Works – Philosophy
Archived 11 January 2012 at the Wayback Machine
84. ^ B Jowett, Menexenus: Appendix I (1st paragraph) Archived 24 September 2015 at the Wayback Machine.
85. ^ See Guthrie 1986; Vlastos 1991; Penner 1992; Kahn 1996; Fine 1999b.
86. ^ Dodds 2004.
87. ^
Cooper 1997, p. xiv.
88. ^ Cooper 1997.
89. ^ Kraut 2013; Schofield 2002; and Rowe 2006.
90. ^ Rodriguez-Grandjean 1998.
91. ^ Reale 1990. Cf. p. 14 and onwards.
92. ^ Krämer 1990. Cf. pp. 38–47.
93. ^ Phaedrus 276c
94. ^ Physics 209b
95. ^
Jump up to:a b Metaphysics 987b
96. ^ Gomperz 1931.
97. ^ Gaiser 1998.
98. ^ C.U. M.Smith – Brain, Mind and Consciousness in the History of Neuroscience (page 1) Archived 23 December 2016 at the Wayback Machine Springer Science & Business, 1
January 2014, 374 pages, Volume 6 of History, philosophy and theory of the life sciences SpringerLink : Bücher ISBN 94-017-8774-3 [Retrieved 27 June 2015]
99. ^ See Burrell 1998 and Hasse 2002, pp. 33–45.
100. ^ Carrigan, Henry L. Jr. (2012) [2011].
“Cambridge Platonists”. The Encyclopedia of Christian Civilization. Chichester, West Sussex: Wiley-Blackwell. doi:10.1002/9780470670606.wbecc0219. ISBN 978-1405157629.
101. ^ Einstein 1949, pp. 683–684.
102. ^ “A.N Whitehead on Plato”. Columbia
College.
103. ^ Fine 1979, p. 366.
Primary sources (Greek and Roman)
• Apuleius, De Dogmate Platonis, I. See original text in Latin Library.
• Aristophanes, The Wasps. See original text in Perseus program.
• Aristotle, Metaphysics. See original
text in Perseus program.
• Cicero, De Divinatione, I. See original text in Latin library.
• Laërtius, Diogenes (1925). “Plato” . Lives of the Eminent Philosophers. Vol. 1:3. Translated by Hicks, Robert Drew (Two volume ed.). Loeb Classical Library.
• Plato.
Charmides . Translated by Jowett, Benjamin – via Wikisource. See original text in Perseus program.
• Plato. Gorgias . Translated by Jowett Benjamin – via Wikisource. See original text in Perseus program.
• Plato (1903). Parmenides. Translated
by Burnet, John. Oxford University. republished by: Crane, Gregory (ed.). “Perseus Digital Library Project”.
• Plato. The Republic . Translated by Jowett Benjamin – via Wikisource. See original text in Perseus program.
• Plutarch (1683) [written
in the late 1st century]. “Pericles” . Lives. Translated by Dryden, John – via Wikisource. See original text in Perseus program.
• Seneca the Younger. Moral Letters to Lucilius: Letter 58 . Translated by Richard Mott Gummere – via Wikisource. See
original text in Latin Library.
• Thucydides. History of the Peloponnesian War . Translated by Crawley, Richard – via Wikisource., V, VIII. See original text in Perseus program.
• Xenophon, Memorabilia. See original text in Perseus program.
Secondary
sources
• Albert, Karl (1980). Griechische Religion und platonische Philosophie. Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag.
• Albert, Karl (1996). Einführung in die philosophische Mystik. Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft.
• Allen, Michael J.B.
(1975). “Introduction”. Marsilio Ficino: The Philebus Commentary. University of California Press. pp. 1–58.
• Baird, Forrest E.; Kaufmann, Walter, eds. (2008). Philosophic Classics: From Plato to Derrida (Fifth ed.). Upper Saddle River, New Jersey:
Pearson Prentice Hall. ISBN 978-0-13-158591-1.
• Blackburn, Simon (1996). The Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy. Oxford University Press.
• Bloom, Harold (1982). Agon. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
• Blössner, Norbert (2007). “The City-Soul
Analogy”. In Ferrari, G.R.F. (ed.). The Cambridge Companion to Plato’s Republic. Translated by G.R.F. Ferrari. Cambridge University Press.
• Borody, W.A. (1998). “Figuring the Phallogocentric Argument with Respect to the Classical Greek Philosophical
Tradition”. Nebula, A Netzine of the Arts and Science. 13: 1–27.
• Boyer, Carl B. (1991). Merzbach, Uta C. (ed.). A History of Mathematics (Second ed.). John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 978-0-471-54397-8.
• Brandwood, Leonard (1990). The Chronology of
Plato’s Dialogues. Cambridge University Press.
• Brickhouse, Thomas; Smith, Nicholas D. Fieser, James; Dowden, Bradley (eds.). “Plato”. The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 3 April 2014.
• Browne, Sir Thomas (1672). “XII”. Pseudodoxia
Epidemica. Vol. IV (6th ed.).
• Brumbaugh, Robert S.; Wells, Rulon S. (October 1989). “Completing Yale’s Microfilm Project”. The Yale University Library Gazette. 64 (1/2): 73–75. JSTOR 40858970.
• Burnet, John (1911). Plato’s Phaedo. Oxford
University Press.
• Burnet, John (1928a). Greek Philosophy: Part I: Thales to Plato. MacMillan.
• Burnet, John (1928b). Platonism. University of California Press.
• Cairns, Huntington (1961). “Introduction”. In Hamilton, Edith; Cairns, Huntington
(eds.). The Collected Dialogues of Plato, Including the Letters. Princeton University Press.
• Burrell, David (1998). “Platonism in Islamic Philosophy”. In Craig, Edward (ed.). Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Vol. 7. Routledge. pp. 429–430.
• Cooper,
John M.; Hutchinson, D.S., eds. (1997). Plato: Complete Works. Hackett Publishing.
• Dillon, John (2003). The Heirs of Plato: A Study of the Old Academy. Oxford University Press.
• Dodds, E.R. (1959). Plato Gorgias. Oxford University Press.
• Dodds,
E.R. (2004) [1951]. The Greeks and the Irrational. University of California Press.
• Dorter, Kenneth (2006). The Transformation of Plato’s Republic. Lexington Books.
• Einstein, Albert (1949). “Remarks to the Essays Appearing in this Collective
Volume”. In Schilpp (ed.). Albert Einstein: Philosopher-Scientist. The Library of Living Philosophers. Vol. 7. MJF Books. pp. 663–688.
• Fine, Gail (July 1979). “Knowledge and Logos in the Theaetetus”. Philosophical Review. 88 (3): 366–397. doi:10.2307/2184956.
JSTOR 2184956. Reprinted in Fine 2003.
• Fine, Gail (1999a). “Selected Bibliography”. Plato 1: Metaphysics and Epistemology. Oxford University Press. pp. 481–494.
• Fine, Gail (1999b). “Introduction”. Plato 2: Ethics, Politics, Religion, and the
Soul. Oxford University Press. pp. 1–33.
• Fine, Gail (2003). “Introduction”. Plato on Knowledge and Forms: Selected Essays. Oxford University Press.
• Gadamer, Hans-Georg (1980) [1968]. “Plato’s Unwritten Dialectic”. Dialogue and Dialectic.
Yale University Press. pp. 124–155.
• Gadamer, Hans-Georg (1997). “Introduzione”. In Girgenti, Giuseppe (ed.). La nuova interpretazione di Platone. Milan: Rusconi Libri.
• Gaiser, Konrad (1980). “Plato’s Enigmatic Lecture ‘On the Good'”. Phronesis.
25 (1): 5–37. doi:10.1163/156852880×00025.
• Gaiser, Konrad (1998). Reale, Giovanni (ed.). Testimonia Platonica: Le antiche testimonianze sulle dottrine non scritte di Platone. Milan: Vita e Pensiero. First published as “Testimonia Platonica. Quellentexte
zur Schule und mündlichen Lehre Platons” as an appendix to Gaiser’s Platons Ungeschriebene Lehre, Stuttgart, 1963.
• Gomperz, H. (1931). “Plato’s System of Philosophy”. In Ryle, G. (ed.). Proceedings of the Seventh International Congress of Philosophy.
London. pp. 426–431. Reprinted in Gomperz, H. (1953). Philosophical Studies. Boston: Christopher Publishing House 1953, pp. 119–124.
• Grondin, Jean (2010). “Gadamer and the Tübingen School”. In Gill, Christopher; Renaud, François (eds.). Hermeneutic
Philosophy and Plato: Gadamer’s Response to the Philebus. Academia Verlag. pp. 139–156.
• Guthrie, W.K.C. (1986). A History of Greek Philosophy: Volume 4, Plato: The Man and His Dialogues: Earlier Period. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-31101-4.
• Hasse,
Dag Nikolaus (2002). “Plato Arabico-latinus”. In Gersh; Hoenen (eds.). The Platonic Tradition in the Middle Ages: A Doxographic Approach. De Gruyter. pp. 33–66.
• Irwin, T.H. (1979). Plato: Gorgias. Oxford University Press.
• Irwin, T.H. (2011).
“The Platonic Corpus”. In Fine, G. (ed.). The Oxford Handbook of Plato. Oxford University Press.
• Jones, Daniel (2006). Roach, Peter; Hartman, James; Setter, Jane (eds.). Cambridge English Pronouncing Dictionary (17 ed.). Cambridge University Press.
• Kahn,
Charles H. (1996). Plato and the Socratic Dialogue: The Philosophical Use of a Literary Form. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-64830-1.
• Kierkegaard, Søren (1992). “Plato”. The Concept of Irony. Princeton University Press. ISBN 978-0-691-02072-3.
• Krämer,
Hans Joachim (1990). Catan, John R. (ed.). Plato and the Foundations of Metaphysics: A Work on the Theory of the Principles and Unwritten Doctrines of Plato with a Collection of the Fundamental Documents. State University of New York Press. ISBN 978-0-7914-0433-1.
• Lee,
M.-K. (2011). “The Theaetetus”. In Fine, G. (ed.). The Oxford Handbook of Plato. Oxford University Press. pp. 411–436.
• Kraut, Richard (11 September 2013). Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). “Plato”. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford University.
Retrieved 3 April 2014.
• Lackner, D. F. (2001). “The Camaldolese Academy: Ambrogio Traversari, Marsilio Ficino and the Christian Platonic Tradition”. In Allen; Rees (eds.). Marsilio Ficino: His Theology, His Philosophy, His Legacy. Brill.
• Meinwald,
Constance Chu (1991). Plato’s Parmenides. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
• McDowell, J. (1973). Plato: Theaetetus. Oxford University Press.
• McEvoy, James (1984). “Plato and The Wisdom of Egypt”. Irish Philosophical Journal. 1 (2): 1–24. doi:10.5840/irishphil1984125.
ISSN 0266-9080. Archived from the original on 5 December 2007. Retrieved 3 December 2007.
• Montoriola, Karl Markgraf von (1926). Briefe Des Mediceerkreises Aus Marsilio Ficino’s Epistolarium. Berlin: Juncker.
• Nails, Debra (2002). The People
of Plato: A Prosopography of Plato and Other Socratics. Hackett Publishing. ISBN 978-0-87220-564-2.
• Nails, Debra (2006). “The Life of Plato of Athens”. In Benson, Hugh H. (ed.). A Companion to Plato. Blackwell Publishing. ISBN 978-1-4051-1521-6.
• Nietzsche,
Friedrich Wilhelm (1967). “Vorlesungsaufzeichnungen”. Werke: Kritische Gesamtausgabe (in German). Walter de Gruyter. ISBN 978-3-11-013912-9.
• Notopoulos, A. (April 1939). “The Name of Plato”. Classical Philology. 34 (2): 135–145. doi:10.1086/362227.
S2CID 161505593.
• Penner, Terry (1992). “Socrates and the Early Dialogues”. In Kraut, Richard (ed.). The Cambridge Companion to Plato. Cambridge University Press. pp. 121–169.
• Meinwald, Constance (16 June 2023). “Plato”. Britannica Online.
• “Plato”.
Encyclopaedic Dictionary The Helios Volume XVI (in Greek). 1952.
• “Plato”. Suda.
• Popper, K. (1962). The Open Society and its Enemies. Vol. 1. London: Routledge.
• Press, Gerald Alan (2000). “Introduction”. In Press, Gerald Alan (ed.). Who
Speaks for Plato?: Studies in Platonic Anonymity. Rowman & Littlefield. pp. 1–14.
• Reale, Giovanni (1990). Catan, John R. (ed.). Plato and Aristotle. A History of Ancient Philosophy. Vol. 2. State University of New York Press.
• Reale, Giovanni
(1997). Toward a New Interpretation of Plato. Washington, DC: CUA Press.
• Riginos, Alice (1976). Platonica : the anecdotes concerning the life and writings of Plato. Leiden: E.J. Brill. ISBN 978-90-04-04565-1.
• Robinson, John (1827). Archæologica
Græca (Second ed.). London: A. J. Valpy. Archived from the original on 1 July 2014. Retrieved 4 February 2017.
• Rodriguez-Grandjean, Pablo (1998). Philosophy and Dialogue: Plato’s Unwritten Doctrines from a Hermeneutical Point of View. Twentieth
World Congress of Philosophy. Boston.
• Rowe, Christopher (2006). “Interpreting Plato”. In Benson, Hugh H. (ed.). A Companion to Plato. Blackwell Publishing. pp. 13–24.
• Schall, James V. (Summer 1996). “On the Death of Plato”. The American Scholar.
65. Archived from the original on 6 August 2020. Retrieved 11 September 2011.
• Schofield, Malcolm (23 August 2002). Craig, Edward (ed.). “Plato”. Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge. Archived from the original on 10 October 2008. Retrieved
3 April 2014.
• Sedley, David (2003). Plato’s Cratylus. Cambridge University Press.
• Slings, S.R. (1987). “Remarks on Some Recent Papyri of the Politeia”. Mnemosyne. Fourth. 40 (1/2): 27–34. doi:10.1163/156852587×00030.
• Slings, S.R. (2003).
Platonis Rempublicam. Oxford University Press.
• Smith, William (1870). “Plato”. Dictionary of Greek and Roman Biography and Mythology. Archived from the original on 24 January 2015. Retrieved 27 January 2007.
• Strauss, Leo (1964). The City and
the Man. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
• Suzanne, Bernard (8 March 2009). “The Stephanus edition”. Plato and his dialogues. Retrieved 3 April 2014.
• Szlezak, Thomas A. (1999). Reading Plato. Routledge. ISBN 978-0-415-18984-2.
• Tarán,
Leonardo (1981). Speusippus of Athens. Brill Publishers.
• Tarán, Leonardo (2001). “Plato’s Alleged Epitaph”. Collected Papers 1962–1999. Brill Academic Publishers. ISBN 978-90-04-12304-5.
• Taylor, Alfred Edward (2001) [1937]. Plato: The Man
and His Work. Courier Dover Publications. ISBN 978-0-486-41605-2.
• Taylor, C.C.W. (2011). “Plato’s Epistemology”. In Fine, G. (ed.). The Oxford Handbook of Plato. Oxford University Press. pp. 165–190.
• Vlastos, Gregory (1991). Socrates: Ironist
and Moral Philosopher. Cambridge University Press.
• Whitehead, Alfred North (1978). Process and Reality. New York: The Free Press.
• Wilamowitz-Moellendorff, Ulrich von (2005) [1917]. Plato: His Life and Work (translated in Greek by Xenophon
Armyros). Kaktos. ISBN 978-960-382-664-4.
Photo credit: https://www.flickr.com/photos/archetypefotografie/4820415253/’]